Wednesday, March 11, 2015

Life After Death in Hinduism



Interviews on Life After Death in Hinduism 
By Rev. Bro. Jesiah Roninson
On 9th of March 2015







 Interview
Chithra Amma, Chief Organizer, Saism, Kandy.
 Interview
Madhirooba Sarma, pradhana Gurukkal, Shivan Kovil, Kandy.
 Interview
Rajeswary, a servant in Kovil, Nawalapitiya.
 Interview
Rohini, a servant in Kovil, Mahaiyawa.
 Interview
Solaiyammah, a servant in Kovil, Kandy.
 Saism 
 Group prayer cum Bajan

Friday, January 16, 2015

Scope of Epistemology

The Scope of Epistemology





1942
Φιλοφια Βιου Κυβερνητης


Epistemology: (Gr. episteme, knowledge + logos, theory) The branch of philosophy which investigates the origin, structure, methods and validity of knowledge. The term "epistemology" appears to have been used for the first time by J. F. Ferrier, Institutes of Metaphysics (1854) who distinguished two branches of philosophy -- epistemology and ontology. The German equivalent of epistemology, Erkenntnistheorie, was used by the Kantian, K. L. Reinhold, (1789); Das Fundament des philosophischen Wissens (1791), but the term did not gain currency until after its adoption by E. Zeller, Ueber Aufgabe und Bedeutung der Erkenntnisstheorie (1862). The term theory of knowledge is a common English equivalent of epistemology and translation of Erkenntnistheorie; the term Gnosiology has also been suggested but has gained few adherents.

The scope of epistemology may be indicated by considering its relations to the allied disciplines: (a) metaphysics, (b) logic, and (c) psychology.


(a) Speculative philosophy is commonly considered to embrace metaphysics (see Metaphysics) and epistemology as its two coordinate branches or if the term metaphysics be extended to embrace the whole of speculative philosophy, then epistemology and ontology become the two main subdivisions of metaphysics in the wide sense. Whichever usage is adopted, epistemology as the philosophical theory of knowledge is one of the two main branches of philosophy. The question of the relative priority of epistemology and metaphysics (or ontology) has occasioned considerable controversy: the dominant view fostered by Descartes, Locke and Kant is that epistemology is the prior philosophical science, the investigation of the possibility and limits of knowledge being a necessary and indispensible preliminary to any metaphysical speculations regarding the nature of ultimate reality. On the other hand, strongly metaphysical thinkers like Spinoza and Hegel, and more recently S. Alexander and A. N. Whitehead, have first attacked the metaphvsical problems and adopted the view of knowledge consonant with their metaphysics. Between these two extremes is the view that epistemology and metaphysics are logically interdependent and that a metaphysically presuppositionless epistemology is as unattainable as an epistemologically presuppositionless metaphysics.


(b) Despite the fact that traditional logic embraced many topics which would now be considered epistemological, the demarcation between logic and epistemology is now fairly clear-cut: logic is the formal science of the principles governing valid reasoning; epistemology is the philosophical science of the nature of knowledge and truth. For example, though the decision as to whether a given process of reasoning is valid or not is a logical question, the inquiry into the nature of validity is epistemological.


(c) The relation between psychology and epistemology is particularly intimate since the cognitive processes of perception, memory, imagination, conception and reasoning, investigated by empirical psychology are the very processes which, in quite a different context, are the special subject matter of epistemology. Nevertheless the psychological and epistemological treatments of the cognitive processes of mind are radically different: scientific psychology is concerned solely with the description and explanation of conscious processes, e.g. particular acts of perception, in the context of other conscious events; epistemology is interested in the cognitive pretentions of the perceptions, i.e. their apparent reference to external objects. In short, whereas psychology is the investigation of all states of mind including the cognitive in the context of the mental life, epistemology investigates only cognitive states and these solely with respect to their cognitive import. Psychology and epistemology are by virtue of the partial identity of their subject matter interdependent sciences. The psychology of perception, memory, imagination, conception, etc. affords indispensable data for epistemological interpretation and on the other hand epistemological analysis of the cognitive processes may sometimea prove psychologically suggestive. The epistemologist must, however, guard against a particularly insidious form of the genetic fallacy: viz. the supposition that the psychological origin of an item of knowledge prejudices either favorably or unfavorably its cognitive validity -- a fallacy which is psychologism at its worst.


An examination of the generally recognized problems of epistemology and of the representative solutions of these problems will serve to further clarify the nature and scope of epistemological inquiry. The emphasis in epistemology has varied from one historical era to another and yet there is a residium of epistemological problems which has persisted to the present.


(a) The initial and inescapable problem with which the epistemologist is confronted is that of the very possibility of knowledge: Is genuine knowledge at all attainable? The natural dogmatism of the human mind is confronted with the sceptic's challenge: a challenge grounded on the relativity of the senses (sensory scepticism) and the contradictions into which the reason is often betrayed (rational scepticism). An alternative to both dogmatism and extreme scepticism is a tentative or methodological scepticism of which Descartes' systematic doubt, Locke's cautious empiricism and Kant's critical epistemology are instances. See Dogmatism; Scepticism; Criticism. Scepticism in modern epistemology is commonly associated with solipsism, since a scepticism regarding knowledge of the external world leads to solipsism and the ego-centric predicament. See Solipsism; Ego-centric predicament.


(b) An epistemologist who rejects an extreme or agnostic scepticism, may very properly seek to determine the limits of knowledge and to assert that genuine knowledge is, within certain prescribed limits, possible yet beyond those limits impossible. There are, of course, innumerable ways of delimiting the knowable from the unknowable -- a typical instance of the sceptical delimitation of knowledge is the Kantian distinction between the phenomenal and noumenal world. See Phenomenon; Noumenon. A similar epistemological position is involved in the doctrine of certain recent positivists and radical empiricists that the knowable coincides with the meaningful and the verifiable, the unknowable with trie meaningless and unverifiable. See Positivism, Logical; Empiricism, Radical.


(c) The traditional problem of the origin of knowledge, viz. By what faculty or faculties of mind is knowledge attainable? It gave rise to the principal cleavage in modern epistemology between rationalism and empiricism (q.v.) though both occur in any thinker. The rationalists (Descartes, Spinoza, Leibniz) rely primarily -- though not exclusively -- on reason as the source of genuine knowledge, and the empiricists (Locke, Berkeley and Hume) rely mainly on experience. A broadly conceived empiricism such as Locke's which acknowledges the authenticity of knowledge derived both from the inner sense (see Reflection; Introspection), and the outer senses, contrasts with that type of sensationalism (q.v.) which is empiricism restricted to the outer senses. Various attempts, the most notable of which is the critical philosophy of Kant, have been made to reconcile rationalism and empiricism by assigning to reason and experience their respective roles in the constitution of knowledge. Few historical or contemporary epistemologists would subscribe either to a rationalism or an empiricism of an exclusive and extreme sort.


(d) The methodological problem bulks large in epistemology and the solutions of it follow in general the lines of cleavage determined by the previous problem. Rationalists of necessity have emphasized deductive and demonstrative procedures in the acquisition and elaboration of knowledge while empiricists have relied largely on induction and hypothesis but few philosophers have espoused the one method to the complete exclusion of the other. A few attempts have been made to elaborate distinctively philosophical methods reducible neither to the inductive procedure of the natural sciences nor the demonstrative method of mathematics -- such are the Transcendental Method of Kant and the Dialectical Method of Hegel though the validity and irreducibility of both of these methods are highly questionable. Pragmatism, operationalism, and phenomenology may perhaps in certain of their aspects be construed is recent attempts to evaluate new epistemological methods.


(e) The problem of the A PRIORI, though the especial concern of the rationalist, confronts the empiricist also since few epistemologists are prepared to exclude the a priori entirely from their accounts of knowledge. The problem is that of isolating the a priori or non-empirical elements in knowledge and accounting for them in terms of the human reason. Three principal theories of the a priori have been advanced:

1.      the theory of the intrinsic A PRIORI which asserts that the basic principles of logic, mathematics, natural sciences and philosophy are self-evident truths recognizable by such intrinsic traits as clarity and distinctness of ideas. The intrinsic theory received its definitive modern expression in the theory of "innate ideas" (q.v.) of Herbert of Cherbury, Descartes, and 17th century rationalism.
2.      The presuppositional theory of the a priori which validates a priori truths by demonstrating that they are presupposed either by their attempted denial (Leibniz) or by the very possibility of experience (Kant).
3.      The postulational theory of the A PRIORI elaborated under the influence of recent postulational techniques in mathematics, interprets a priori principles as rules or postulates arbitrarily posited in the construction of formal deductive systems. See Postulate; Posit.
(f) The problem of differentiating the principal kinds of knowledge is an essential task especially for an empirical epistemology. Perhaps the most elementary epistemological distinction is between

1.      non-inferential apprehension of objects by perception, memory, etc. (see Knowledge by Acquaintance), and
2.      inferential knowledge of things with which the knowing subject has no direct apprehension. See Knowledge by Description.
Acquaintance in turn assumes two principal forms: perception or acquaintance with external objects (see Perception), and introspection or the subject's acquaintance with the "self" and its cognitive, volitional and affective states. See IntrospectionReflection. Inferential knowledge includes knowledge of other selves (this is not to deny that knowledge of other minds may at times be immediate and non-inferential),historical knowledge, including not only history in the narrower sense but also astronomical, biological, anthropological and archaeological and even cosmological reconstructions of the past and finally scientific knowledge in so far as it involves inference and construction from observational data.

(g) The problem of the structure of the knowledge-situation is to determine with respect to each of the major kinds of knowledge just enumerated -- but particularly with respect to perception -- the constituents of the knowledge-situation in their relation to one another. The structural problem stated in general but rather vague terms is: What is the relation between the subjective and objective components of the knowledge-situation? In contemporary epistemology, the structural problem has assumed a position of such preeminence as frequently to eclipse other issues of epistemology. The problem has even been incorporated by some into the definition of philosophy. (See A. Lalande, Vocabulaire de la Philosophie, art. Theorie de la Connaissance. I. and G.D. Hicks, Encycl. Brit. 5th ed. art. Theory of Knowledge.) The principal cleavage in epistemology, according to this formulation of its problem, is between a subjectivism which telescopes the object of knowledge into the knowing subject (see SubjectivismIdealism, Epistemological) and pan-objectivism which ascribes to the object all qualities perceived or otherwise cognized. See Pan-obiectivism. A compromise between the extrernes of subjectivism and objectivism is achieved by the theory of representative perception, which, distinguishing between primary and secondary qualities, considers the former objective, the latter subjective. See Representative PerceptionTheory of; Primary Qualities;Secondary Qualities.
The structural problem stated in terms of the antithesis between subjective and objective is rather too vague for the purposes of epistemology and a more precise analysis of the knowledge-situation and statement of the issues involved is required. The perceptual situation -- and this analysis may presumably be extended with appropriate modifications to memory, imagination and other modes of cognition -- consists of asubject (the self, or pure act of perceiving), the content (sense data) and the object (the physical thing perceived). In terms of this analysis, two issues may be formulated

1.      Are content and object identical (epistemological monism), or are they numerically distinct (epistemological dualism)? and
2.      Does the object exist independently of the knowing subject (epistemological idealism) or is it dependent upon the subject (epistemological realism)?
(h) The problem of truth is perhaps the culmination of epistemological enquiry -- in any case it is the problem which brings the enquiry to the threshold of metaphysics. The traditional theories of the nature of truth are:

1.     

Friday, January 2, 2015

Angelic Eve

 Angelic Eve, the annual Carol service of the Philosophate of the National seminary of Our Lady of Lanka was held on 18th of December 2014 at the Philosophate.

Sunday, November 23, 2014

The widow's offering

The widow's offering

41 Jesus sat down opposite the place where the offerings were put and watched the crowd putting their money into the temple treasury.

Saturday, November 15, 2014

Sunday Sermons


 God speaks through Gospels where He expresses His divine will to human beings.  Before we start reading any biblical passage, our minds must be first conceived of the biblical, geographical, historical and theological background which will help us understand the passage meaningfully taking into consideration each and every aspect. Then only the true meaning will be brought forth.



            Today’s Gospel is taken from the Gospel of St. Mathew 25:14-30

Monday, November 10, 2014

THE ICONOGRAPHY OF LORD ḲṚṢṆA

HINDUISM:

THE ICONOGRAPHY OF LORD ḲṚṢṆA

கி ரு ஷ் ணா, க ண் ண ன் 

Man is a rational animal who found it difficult at a point to control some natural events and eventually fell into the submission of nature and personified it with his same rational interpretation. He developed his spiritual substance into an organized orderly system which he called ‘Religion’ from where onwards his inborn quest continues with acceleration to know the Divine.

Therefore his attempt to a lively actualization of ‘God’ brought forth symbolic or iconographical interpretation along with the sculptural and portrayal depiction or exposition of the above. Hinduism has been highly compared with this concept, of which this discussion goes, for the reason that it still has the original attempt of man in personification of his spiritual entity. For the naive view, this many-god religion never fails to give sufficient information or rather description to all its gods through iconography.

Lord Krishna, one among the many Avatārs of Lord Vishnu who was an emitted prince of Kamsa was brought up by the leader of a cowherd.  He later killed his father with Balarāman his step- brother and obtained the kingship in Dvārakā.  He was a divinized person who met with an actual death in his last phase of life.  But, however on his insistence, the pastoral community was converted from Indra worship into Vaisnavism and added to that for his triumphant rule he was believed to be an Avatār.  All his life was written down and put in art and sculpture describing his nature through the iconographical explanation.  There many forms of symbolic expression namely, diagrammatical and emblematic, pictorial, gestural and physical movements, verbal, musical, conjunction and combination of various modes.
            The iconography of Krishnā can be defined in many ways in accordance to the artist who makes it with the intention of expressing something.  In that way nature takes a prominent place.  Krishnā is depicted as a child, showing his opened mouth in which the whole universe is seen. This is connected to an event happened during his childhood that tries to say that the whole universe was created by Vishnu and he controls the ‘time’; Lord Shiva destroys the world once the circle is over whereas Vishnu becomes the cause of re-creation by first bringing forth Brahmā, the creator god.  It also reminds of his another famous Avatār,  Vāmana who measured the whole three worlds with only three steps (Satapatha Brāhmana xiv, 1,1,6).  In another form he is depicted as a boy who stands on the top of a poly headed snake in water.  Water (Āpah)  is an integral reality, therefore, has healing power (Cf. RV x, 137,6; AV ii,3,6; vi,91,3; SB iii,6,1,7)Purification is their first anthropocosmic function.
            Another point of discussion would be the human relationship which is mostly the family bonds such as mother and child and father and child. These portrayals try to explain the relationship or intimacy between God and man that is done with one depiction showing Yashodā holding child Krishnā. The mother image is closely bound up with Earth symbolism, vegetation, agriculture, fertility, the reappearance of life and the lunar cycle. The image of the child, the subject, or slave again indicate man’s relationship to God; the image of the ruler (Encyclopaedia Brittanica, macropaedia, vol. 17, 15th edition, pp 908).  Therefore the above expression is found in that image.

The next on the topic is the unavoidable part of human life, the sexuality which also has been used to carry message.  Lord Krishnā is seemed to be a mischievous man in his youth who plays fool with gopis, the girls of the pastoral community. Some pictures show naked gopis who are having bath while Krishna refused to give the cloths to them.  These try to say the analogy between divine love and human love. Divine lover is shown playing the flute, surrounded by adoring maidens and cows. People must be attracted towards god having genuine love for him as it is shown.  Vaisnavite theology brings forth this idea that we also find in saivism in the formless form of Shivalingam (Linga-Yoni symbolism) which is the complete power results in the combination of Shiva and Shakthi and the same was done with Krishna and Rādhā.  Here, the cow is seen in most of the images and sculptures standing for prosperity because, the cow is considered a god called Kāmadhēnu that is in Dhēvalokha. The animal form is the representation of Divine (theriomorphism, or zoomorphism).  
            Culture also influences the formation of iconography for the reason that the artist is already influenced by it. This can be evidently seen in the images of Krishnā in which he is depicted as a child dances on the snake and so on. The people of the pastoral community were in fear of fearful animals so that, he is seen as it is said above and also cow is mostly shown because that was their bread winning job. Hunters, farmers, shepherds, artisans and merchants and their activities are represented in religious pictures and appear in verbal symbolism of religion (Encyclopaedia Brittanica, macropaedia, vol. 17, 15th edition, pp 908).
            Conceptual influences are widely seen in the incorporation of ideas, theories and structured system of thought into images. The conflict with Indra worship is substituted by Vaisnavite theological inputs which are shown in the image depicting child Krishna showing the universe in his mouth. Krishnā as he preaches the Gitā is the best example for this in which he is shown as the protector and preacher of Dharma giving instructions to Arjun. It is an example also for the Chrematomorphic motifs that places holy books or scriptures and objects.
Though the images and sculptures are apparently normal they have a treasured meaning with them in their iconography. These religious concepts have been abbreviated in the iconography of pictures and simplified to be given to the people with a message to say.  Krishanā was a triumphant king and a good human being whereas the divinization of this King initiated a new branch of Hinduism called Krishnaism still followed by North Indians and the same happened with King Rama. Krishna was just a reformer or rather a new god who changed the Indra-dominated Vedic religion among the pastoral community into Vaisnavism.  His life is fully narrated in Bhāgavata Purāna but not much in Vedas. All his images bring some news or specific interpretations with them and all of them are mostly hybrid motifs.  It is the core of this codification that the people who look at the work god experience is given. Therefore Krishna’s iconography becomes useful in order to understand him better.



-An Assignment submitted to REVD. FR. DEVIN COONGHE IVD